On Assassin’s Creed 2 – Interface

This is the third of three essays in a series on Assassin’s Creed 2, which is itself part of a much larger series on the Assassin’s Creed franchise itself.

Assassin’s Creed uses the mechanic of blending in order to allow Altair, the assassin of the Holy Land in the middle ages, to hide within groups of monks and healers of the cities. For that first game, that’s as far as that mechanic goes; it is a scalpel-like application of a single ability in a game that is all about finite uses for specific abilities (as I’ve argued previously). ezio

The blending with the monks in Assassin’s Creed is meant to be an illustration of the methodology of the assassin’s themselves, as undetectability-until-too-late is the primary mode of attack that the group uses throughout the series and in all of its various incarnations down through the centuries. Just watch the trailer for the first game to really understand this — Altair kills, runs, and then disperses himself into the public through the bodies of the monks (which also fuels a hatred of religious orders later in the game).

This small amount of backtracking is important to do in order to point out how Assassin’s Creed 2 changes the use of blending. No longer is it a single-use escape plan. Instead it is a crucial way of being in the world. Ezio is constantly walking into groups of people, or standing behind them, or touching them as he walks through their tight-knit groupings. We can imagine a step left out, a quick introduction, Ezio acting as if he knows these people in the short moment it takes to make sure that the guard you’re tailing to look away from you.

Altair disperses himself into a silent group who eliminated all of their personal characteristics in order to become just that — an order.

Ezio disperses himself into a raucous, heterogeneous group who are all functionally identical in their difference. They are not an order; they are a crowd.

This progression of modernity into a weird, radical sameness (or infinite replaceability) was as much a bugbear of the early Modern period as it seems to be now; people want to be understood as different, and that quest for radical difference has always eaten itself like some infinitely predictable Ourobouros (see: normcore). That’s old hat and well-trod ground, though, so I’m interested in where that can take us if we take blending one step further out and into the interface.

The interfaces of Assassin’s Creed and Assassin’s Creed 2 are significantly different in a few ways, with the most important (and the only one I’m going to talk about here) one being the use of synchronization as a health bar. Carol Pinchefsky explains:

In AC1, there’s no such thing as health or armor. There’s just synchronization—how close you (Desmond Miles) could faithfully recreate the actions of ancestor Altair. If you got hurt or fell off a building, you lost synchronization. Why? Because you suck, I mean, you weren’t as good an assassin as Altair, that’s why. The real Altair was too nimble to fall of a building, too stealthy to attract attention, and more lethal than Agent 47 (ooo, I went there). That’s why killing bystanders also cost you synchronization: You weren’t performing compatibly with the memory you were trying to retrieve. It’s a brilliant concept.

The sequels totally miss the point of how synchronization drives the first game. They introduce actual health, which could be restored with health tonics. In other words, medieval assassin Ezio actually does get thwacked upside the head by that Brute, no matter what you “remembered” him doing. (This means that Altair, who did not miss his jumps, is a definitively better assassin than Ezio. Ooo, I went there again.)

As Pinchefsky notes, the general gist here is that the health system moved from “how close is the player to the reality of history” to “how well is the player performing in a specific set of circumstances.” There’s a significant difference in these two things, and the difference is one of understanding how interfaces themselves work.

In the Assassin’s Creed model, synchronization works the same way as blending: how close can you be to an ideal?

In the Assassin’s Creed 2 model, synchronization also models blending, asking “how well can you fit into this heterogeneous set of conditions where the right way of doing things is not distinguishable from the successful way of doing things?” 

The interface differences here are not merely different modes of dealing with the game. On the contrary, without parsing this out, I’m not sure that much of a difference is even felt between these two systems, especially since blending is such a small part of the first game in the series. What I believe is productive here is to think about what it means for the very mode of interacting with the game (me playing the game) to mimic the process of the assassin living in their world (Ezio becoming part of a crowd). These are what Alexander Galloway, in his The Interface Effect, calls “parallel aesthetic events,” or allegorical relationships between my interactions as a player and the character’s interactions in the game world.

This piece is long, so I will end with a description of those parallel events. I don’t want to drive home a conclusion–I don’t have one–but instead to open up how this process is working.

Ezio is following a target through a market. The market is filled with people wearing different clothing, carrying different things, sitting down and standing up, walking in groups of three to six, speaking and laughing. The target turns. Ezio, a person with literally superhuman powers of reflex and discernment, dodges into a group talking to one another. They have a short conversation. Ezio is no longer a unique superhuman, but instead a person with the fundamental characteristics of a nonplayer character. He is not a figure with a destiny. He is one of many bodies moving and shifting (and it is worth noting that the multiplayer modes for the series from Brotherhood forward depend on this becoming-NPC of the player character).

The parallel aesthetic event:

I am sitting on a couch. I am moving my thumbs and fingers in practiced motions in order to get Ezio to run from building to building in a particular line. Thousands of other people are doing the same thing at the same time. Then we are all doing the final mission. We are fighting the Pope. None of us are unique; we are all compacted into one heterogeneous mass with preserved difference and yet very little difference at all. We are all one of many bodies shifting and moving.

This entry was posted in Assassin's Creed, Video Games and tagged , , , , , . Bookmark the permalink.

3 Responses to On Assassin’s Creed 2 – Interface

  1. Following up on this, I’m interested in what this means from the standpoint of medievalism:

    Altair disperses himself into a silent group who eliminated all of their personal characteristics in order to become just that — an order.
    Ezio disperses himself into a raucous, heterogeneous group who are all functionally identical in their difference. They are not an order; they are a crowd.

    By ‘medievalism’ I mean post-medieval imaginations (especially recreative imaginations, nostalgia and make-believe) of the Middle Ages [though the Middle Ages had its own nostalgia about itself, something that can’t be discussed in this comment]. Now, a standard line about the Middle Ages/Modern difference is that modernity ‘invented’ the individual. Some Early Modernists will still spout this line, and, yes, we can see that there’s a real difference between, say, Jane Austen’s characterizations and those of Chrétien de Troyes. So, my sense is that AC may fall into the standard division of medieval from modern.

    But, because I’ve been watching this lately, I immediately realized that one key difference between the Middle Ages and modernity is the professional army and its key aspect, the uniform. I’m not a military historian, thank god, so grain of salt: but my sense is that military ORDER, with the dedicated drumming out of individuality, has its closest analog in monastic de-individualization, to the extent that, perhaps, the military uniform’s closest analog is the monastic habit [idea of course could be developed by playing with habitus].

    Meanwhile the actual chivalric armies of the high and late middle ages were marked as collectives of individuals through heraldry. In literature, we see them as crowds out of which individuals emerge to show their prowess. They fight in groups but not, I’d say, as groups, at least in literature.

    This means, of course, that the engine of modernity and modern imperialism, the 18th-century (?) army, is, in some key ways, ‘medieval’ at its heart. Meanwhile, religious fervor becomes increasingly ‘individualistic’ with the rise of printing and the explosion of Protestant sects. Periodization needs more work, again.

    From a game play perspective, from someone who hasn’t played these games nor many, I’m wondering what how it would play out for our assassin to don a uniform, disappear into an army, and kill a fellow soldier in the midst of a battle….particularly if his target were on the opposing side. How would this ‘individual’ killing rate within the surrounding general slaughter? What would happen to the story of this hero if, in fact, his killing was just the killing all these normal soldiers were doing anyhow?

    • Mike Sell says:

      Michel Foucault would have a different take on modernity, the individual, and the role of disciplinary institutions like the national army, the factory, etc. These all developed various techniques to ensure both order and efficiency, mostly in the 19th century. There’s a fastest way to load a rifle. There’s a fastest way to make a pin. So, on the face of it, it would seem like the modernity of the mass is the modernity of the 19th century (there are precursors in earlier moments).

      However, the irony that Foucault tracks is that this massification coincides with the rise of new understandings of the individual–with the widespread ideology of individuality encoded in bills of rights, constitutions, the law, etc. And people who served in disciplinary institutions often felt keenly that they were meaningful as individuals, that they were forming both themselves and their nations simultaneously.

      Here’s my point: That last bit about all of us twitching our thumbs simultaneously, twitching as a mass is both the expression of a massification of the group and the massification of individualism. In other words, there’s really no difference between the two. The Assassins Creed series, weirdly, seems to be “working out” this contradiction in its very design.

      • Sure, I’m on board with that aporia. Except I wouldn’t locate it so confidently in the 19th century.

        Why? The one thing Foucault gets wrong — and this is a big one — is the historical sequence. He tends to claim these things began in the 19th century, or the 17th century, depending on what he’s talking about, because these are the periods he knows best. He doesn’t know the medieval archives, so when he talks about the Middle Ages, he tends to make big, and wrong, assumptions about what going on in them.

        For example, Foucault’s biopolitics material makes big claims about the sovereignty preceding biopolitics. This isn’t quite right. Here, maybe obnoxiously, follows an expert from a chapter that’s coming out in the anthology The Politics of Ecology: Land, Life, and Law in Medieval Britain (knock on wood):

        Foucault’s narrative splits the medieval from the modern, taking sovereignty as characteristic of the former and biopolitics of the latter. In a volume largely directed at medievalists, it may be otiose to lay out, once again, the corrections Foucault’s historical narrative requires. For example, when he neatly observes that “throughout the Middle Ages, judicial practice was a multiplier of royal power,” whereas in the “new governmental rationality” of the modern era, “legal theory and judicial institutions no longer serve as the multiplier, but rather as the subtractor of royal power,” 19 Foucault sweeps aside the complications of Ranulf de Glanville’s late twelfth-century Treatise on the Laws and Customs of Realm of England, which sometimes characterizes the king as a Roman despot, at once constituting and above the law, and at other times as himself guided by the laws and his lords. 20 Cataloging more failures of Foucault’s medieval models would be tedious, ungenerous, and small-minded, especially as Foucault himself explains that despite the neatness of his narrative, “in reality you have a series of complex edifices in which, of course, the techniques themselves change and are perfected, or anyway become more complicated, but in which what above all changes is the dominant characteristic.” 21 This at least even the most pedantic medievalist could admit: the disappearance of the king and the rise of the state, with its pretense to impersonal and immaterial existence, does change the dominant ways governmentality operates and presents itself to itself and its subjects. For this paper, the mistake that matters is one to which Foucault never confessed, and which the criticism has only started to track, namely, his anthropocentrism. By leaving most life outside his attention, Foucault missed how biopolitics was the dominant characteristic of, at least, those legal spaces where the post-conquest medieval English king thought he exercised his sovereignty most freely. The paired concerns of the medieval English forest, namely its attempt to monopolize legitimate violence and to oversee cervid wellbeing, frustrates attempts to seal medieval and modern forms of governmentality and indeed sovereignty and biopolitics from each other, because in England at least, the birth of the sovereign is also simultaneously the birth of biopolitics.

Comments are closed.